Sunday, December 9, 2012

Sources of the Self, Charles Taylor


Sources of the Self, Charles Taylor, 1989

Some notes, clarifications, responses, appreciations, counterarguments /SB, 2012

Brief summary: it's good to have someone to argue with; thank you, Charles Taylor, CT; thank you, Eric Springsted, EOS, for sending me to Taylor

(1) review and criticism

(2) EOS - SB

--------------------------------------------------

(1) review and criticism

CT argues against reductionism in many forms, e.g. reducing arguments to mere struggles for power; merely scientistic accounts; mere talk about values.  He wants to recover the diversity of goods that people care about.  He wants to recover the specific character of their commitments.  He wants to recover their heartfelt, unarticulated understandings of what it is like to want something -- which is, to be an agent -- agency as wielding power on behalf of a desired end -- forces aligned to promote a value.

Some of the commitments that he wants to capture in their reality are: the commitment to political justice; the relief of suffering; the love of family; the importance of friends.

Some themes that he derives from Greek scholarship and especially the leadership of A.W.H. Adkins and E.R. Dodds are: from the many to the one (the gradual development of a coherent self from its precursor fragments); enthusiasm and the Homeric background of possession, being overtaken, overwhelmed, being carried away, beside oneself with passion; thumos, psyche, kardia, etor, ker, noos, phrenes, soma, menos (madness); everything in our natures that "wanders between generation and corruption" (Rep 485b).  Adkins' developmental account becomes an important element in the book.  Snell, Schadewaldt, Jaeger, Gilson are here also -- also later scholars such as Walter Burkert, Richard Onians -- also Nietzsche, Nehamas -- also Hannah Arendt. 

A second important strain of influence derives from psychology -- Jerome Bruner, Kohut, Kernberg, Erikson, Ernst Tugenhat, Freud, Foucault -- writers who explore selfhood in its granular construction up from earliest bits of competence (ego nuclei), to stages, to big assemblages of experience, connectivity and idea-formation (durable incorporations).

A third strain is from social philosophy and sociology and concepts of selfhood that bind human to human in social networks -- Marx, Gadamer, Heidegger, Wittgenstein, the Frankfurt school, Humboldt, Weber, Robert Bellah, and especially Aristotle.

            "One cannot be a self on one's own." "I am a self only in virtue of certain interlocators." "I have conversational partners who are essential to my achieving self -definition."  "A self exists within webs of interlocution." (36)

A fourth strain is from storytellers who narrate the struggle to become a self from many corners of transcendence, elation, depression, oppression, dysfunction, illness, and alienation: Joseph Conrad, Kafka, Breton, Goethe, Hoelderlin, D.H. Lawrence, de Sade, Mallarme, Robert Musil, Poe, Pound, Zola, Yeats, Van Gogh, W. Stevens, Dostoyevsky.  CT mines many writers attuned to their rich interior life, who portray this world as discussion and rivalry and conflict -- Pascal, La Rochefoucauld, Marcus Aurelius, Epictetus; poets; generations of ascetics and puritans closely monitoring their sinfulness and daily temptations to stray from the path; journal writers, aphorists; everyone who "makes the dizzying descent into ourselves" (Andre Breton). 

There are conservative icons such as Strauss, Sandel, Augustine, Shaftesbury, Grotius. 

He is fighting against liberal icons such as Socrates, Descartes, Spinoza, John Rawls. 

Terms of art:

constitutive goods (the conceived order of being into which actions flows -- this defines what 'good action' is, the empowering love that urges forward);

disengaged reason (Socratic reason departing from the current ethos; Descartes' pretensions; rationality as conceived in opposition to parochial attachments);

counter-epiphanic (showing things in their crude, lowly reality and disabusing any sentiment of deeper meaning -- the opposite of transfiguration or transcendence);

hypergoods (goods that exemplify and provide the standpoint from which lesser, regular and ordinary kinds of goods are valued -- second-order qualitative distinctions that define and provide the basis of discriminations in value judgment);

inescapable frameworks (defining cultural and social standpoints and codes or forms of life, within which entire epochs unfold historically -- basic horizons; no framework is shared by everyone, no framework can be taken as the framework, no framework can be accorded the status of a fact; instead, we have traditions, ideologies, supercontexts; for which the question arises, whether adopting them is optional?; also, from which we can become disenchanted; which we can leave behind; a frame of commitments and identifications, a shared space of moral concern; that without which, in normal experience, we would be at sea and not know who or what we are, or what the significance of anything might be; which define a narrative by means of which we assign meaning and contemplate new ideas -- the basis projected meaning; a way of talking about structural requirements for human agency which nonetheless do change and which present themselves to philosophy as a problem; which yet we see from the standpoint of the horizon that we ourselves stand within; which CT conceives as a kind of cultural co-embeddedness, directly opposed to the concept of disengaged reason);

            "To articulate a framework is to explicate what makes sense of our moral responses" -- CT gives an example of this at 541 in discussing how the warrior/honor ethic makes sense of Cicero's talk about self-control as manly dignity that steels us against childish, slavish, cowardly, womanly weakness.  The command relation explains the ability to bear pain with equanimity, developing fortitude, soldierly virtue, scorning pain and death.  The framework defines constitutive goods and hypergoods. 

lifegoods (facets or components of life as actually lived, which spell out what is aimed at, in concrete terms, in the context of a cosmic order of being of constitutive goods);

ordinary life (the life of production and the family, merely infrastructurally important to Aristotle, a merely necessary background to the 'good life' of contemplation and action as a citizen; affirmed for the first time as having central importance for the good life via the Reformation, when it is seen as living in the context of a calling -- dethroning the 'higher forms' of life identified in antiquity; putting simple things in the center and underscoring the import of suffering; the key and world-changing focus of Christianity).

With these influences and this new vocabulary, CT contributes to the human project of understanding itself.  He takes on the crucial and mysterious process by which an organism becomes a person.  This big project deserves our respect and critical review…

Some big problem-regions here are: the push-pull of being a one within a many; the long road to integration by which manyness become oneness; the special circumstances in which some one person breaks out from a big framework and begins to live in a different order of being; the life-context of embedded reason vs. the purity of disengaged reason; and tensions between the method and the results of science. 

Some stages of developing selfhood that CT identifies for critical reflection:

Homeric disintegration
Platonic psychological monism and playfulness about psychological polyphony
Augustinian inwardness
Cartesian disengaged reason
Lockean subjectivity of perception
Protestantism and the affirmation of ordinary life
The Enlightenment and reason becoming overconfident and blind to its other
Romanticism, listening to nature and reading nature, expressivism
Modernism, postmodernism, the hodge-podge world and the hodge-podge self; world-
            pieces and self-pieces setting uneasily with each other
The current conflict space -- trying to get clear about the choices in front of us

Tasks: trace the histories of these various self-conceptions; reveal the power these ideas have for us from their deep sources; trace the sources of our inspirations for the many ways we look at things; describe the resultant situation we face in postmodern times; find a way out

Part of this is the Hegelian history of ideas project -- but going beyond Hegel in the Heideggerian claim that rationality is not a disengagement that grasps what the world looks like without us (supposed neutrality or objectivity or scientific truth) but instead reason is a deep part of our humanity with its own special history -- reasoning is something that cultural co-embeddedness instills in new members of our tribe

A basic CT argument: we move through the world via goals (loves, commitments, values) -- thus to see ourselves as agents (and this is what CT is trying to do) is to see ourselves as pursuing what we are after (what we desire, the things we sight in desire, the character revealed in desiring).  Identity is conferred via a person's sense of the good.  This is a bedrock argument in the text.  "To know who I am is a species of knowing where I stand" (27).  "To know who you are is to be oriented in moral space" (28)

Cultural relativism says: evaluation is essentially a projection of local tradition. 

CT wants to fight against this reduction.  He argues: people do not cherish what they do because their tradition tells them to do so.  Instead, they see themselves as striving after what really is good.  CT also argues: people are largely ignorant of, and not too worried about, the various conflicting desires that emerge in even their simplest actions.  He wants to bring more self-consciousness to selfhood. 

CT argues that over a long period of history there emerges the idea of inwardness, inner depth, the whole interior life of thoughts and feelings that has an odd kind of access to itself via reflexivity and self-consciousness.  Joseph Conrad has described in a powerful way these inner reaches which lie at some distance from ordinary mind in a hidden heart of darkness

The Enlightenment self breaks away from nature by setting up a process of scientifically observing nature.  The Romantic self returns to nature and listens to nature and is refreshed and reanimated by nature.  These strains still conflict in us.  There are stresses, tensions.  We cannot put everything we care about and all of our insights, attractions, constructions, into ONE formula, hierarchy, assemblage, in final form. 

More genuinely, the project is to try to do justice to ALL the things we love.  If we do not do this, we "incur a huge self-inflicted wound" (513,520).

Critique:

CT's conclusion advocates a particular way out from the postmodern dilemma but does not argue for it -- he calls it a hunch, an intuition. CT wants to recover the specifically religious sources of value that help us navigate our life-projects -- but this is a hunch and represents CT as advocating a way out, his particular take, rather than the main work of the book, i.e. to lay out the sources of the self and their history (71, 105, 106, 342, 518)

CT has an important insight in grasping that we move through the world via goals.  However, relying on this insight tends to cloud the sense of self that arrives via our mere thinghood and experiences in which one is not being treated as an agent, or seeking good, as value-maker and value-pursuer.  E.g. a human being is someone who makes choices, but a human being is also someone who gets hit by a car.  If the goal is to see selfhood in its wholeness and all its complexity, we have to face the agency/thinghood divide and figure out some ways of getting at this and working with it; the self has lots of "sources"

CT wants to bring self-consciousness to the project of selfhood but at the same time much of the work attacks self-consciousness in its guise of disengaged reason.  The sense of the self that we get from reflecting on our experience needs better integration with the sense of the self that we get by being part of a tradition.  This is a tension throughout the book and is not resolved successfully.  Pascal says: I do not want the God of the philosophers and scholars, but the God of Abraham, Isaac and Jacob.  In a sense, CT has made this mistake.  He has given us the self of the philosophers and scholars. 

Another weakness here is that CT wants to blame cultural relativism, secular humanism and the big complex mess that we face in the postmodern dilemma for people's current sense of meaninglessness, despair, loss of roots, waywardness, alienation, anomie.  But this is absurd, really, and pretty obviously so.  The despair we feel that opens up the chasm of meaninglessness is a legacy of the (now forever lost) centuries-long dependency on religious dogma.  Godlessness is not the result of cultural relativism.  Cultural relativism and the whole big mess of modernism emerge when God dies. 

We used to say (with Aristotle) that if you raise people with love, material support and a good education, then they will be capable of virtue.  CT recognizes that this model does not work anymore because we are more conscious than our ancestors of "the murkier depths of human motivation" (517).  We see how much more than these simple inputs can change the picture.  (This is why the sense of self as non-agent is so important to an integrated conception of the self … we need to bring in chance, fate, politics, economics, intellectual factors, accidents … then we have a better chance of learning the ropes)

There are two poles on opposite sides: a reductionist account, in which explaining means explaining away, and an idealistic account, in which explaining gets us to see that everything depends on us -- on choices, decisions, human agency, the values we live by

There are things we care about and ideas that move us that are really difficult to square with each other.  Just to take one example: CT describes the change from Aristotle to Augustine as progress; but many writers (e.g. Gibbon) argue just the reverse.  Both perspectives are important and insightful.  But they are irresolvable.  There is conflict.  And CT sees that we cannot reduce everything to one measure or tell only one story. 

CT has a huge insight in talking about the good.  If we want to say what it is about human beings that makes them worthy of respect, you have to talk about suffering, about what is repugnant about injustice, about the awe we feel at the dimension of human life.  But argument does not seem to go from a neutral place that everybody can agree about to what CT calls "insights about moral ontology."  What is this ontology?  Maybe it's our imagination at work.  Our instincts.  Our senses.  Our mode of access to the world (the way the world looks to us includes important differences between things and people).  CT blames pluralism for making it too easy for us to hold incompatible moral ideas without trying to square them together and come up with a coherent view.  Pluralism leads to thoughtlessness.  But this seems absurd.  We cannot blame a larger consciousness about the ways people approach the problem of life for making us less rational or less thoughtful or less willing to do the work of trying to resolve contradictions.  The modern condition is crazy-making (like mortality generally) and needs thoughtfulness.  People make their lives thoughtful or no -- not abstractions like pluralism.  Pluralism is just the reality of the variety of frameworks, which variety is irresolvable, as CT himself spells out very clearly.

"Our identity is deeper and more many-sided than any of our possible articulations of it" (29)

CT claims that it is an exclusively modern problem that people are confused about which account of the good makes most sense to them -- or of human nature, of what makes people worthy of respect.  This is absolutely false.  The ancients faced exactly this problem -- probably every age shows us some of this conflict, confusion, struggle … ancient China, ancient India, Melitus, Egypt under Akhenaton, medieval France. 

There are other problems too; CT's account of selfhood is self-avowedly parochial and only addresses the Western self and probably only a small fraction of this kind of experience.  He seems to be arguing that selfhood is contingent at the root and that Indian or Chinese selfhood and other varieties are not covered by his account; and his Western account has been criticized for its monolithic reading of history ("Taylor's account applies only to views that succeed each other within a continuous history," Martha Nussbaum).  For some reason CT quotes Descartes in French even though Descartes wrote in Latin and never approved a French translation of his works. 

Overall: this text makes some huge steps forward and also makes important mistakes.  In my reading, the spirit of helpfulness in this text far exceeds its shortcomings. 

(2) EOS - SB

boss thanks again for taking the time to do this.  In the end we agree about everything essential and as you eloquently state: living without questions is not something that an intelligent person is going to do; we are going to wonder what a person like this is trying to protect; we would worry about them.  'Course people are probably worried about us, too.  Anyhow your final invocation of something like a test of love or by love is cool: love is the guard watching over being assured; love can see when the big thing that a person is trying to affirm and protect has turned into hatred and become destructive.  I like this kind of love and I will block the way to my skepticism.  Some say that love is blind, some that love gives us eyes to see.  I wrote something recently about philosophy and love and I think lovers of learning will like the comparison of questioning to loving -- and assert that some kinds of love keep us sane rather than driving us nuts -- but in another way we also know that love sometimes goes bonkers, and getting your bearings and having some scrap of sanity may be a helpful companion if part of our loving goes nuts.

Certitude as you define it is part of a big whole -- it is a connection to something larger than just oneself.  It's a group feeling, like Ibn Khaldun talks about.  Since its social it is natural to connect it with the kind of love we were talking about above, that understands when devotion to the cause has degenerated into something base.  There is a kind of connectivity and being part of something that palpably incorporates a background orientation ("inescapable framework") and helps to explain judgments that people make unthinkingly on a daily basis.  The problem is how to problematize this background, or open it to revision; how to understand it, how it changes as well as how it endures.  Certitude without questioning degenerates into a condition we will worry about and which may become destructive -- which often has been destructive -- so we will look for a group-feeling that love hopefully reads correctly, and does not lose its head about, and give up the critical project.  This is taking a lot on ourselves but we have no choice -- we have to rely on what we can do -- sometimes we are called upon to be smart about love -- and when we think of ourselves as playing a part of a big whole, we are using our imaginations to help create the common space in which we live our lives (527).

Our author gives us the following opinion: God loveth adverbs; that is, how you do something is everything, not just that you do it.  The critical element is preserved in a way or modulation of conducting or going on with this project -- the project encoded in our inescapable framework.  And this implies some escape, some transcendence, a distancing from "identification with a particular voice" (526), which works like this:

"Transcending the self in the model I am working with here is to escape identification with a particular voice in the conversation … There is no doubt that we have the imaginative power to step beyond our own place and to understand ourselves as playing a part in the whole … what is not clear is to what degree one can actually assume this standpoint and live it … (526-7). 

CT seems to be dismissive of a bunch of recent views that try to deal with the element of transcendence, which he calls "half-baked reflections on language and the impossibility of full presence."  Probably I don't know the references he is getting at in this note, but to me the main thing is any admission of transcendence at all.  If he admits it, then the relationship to the group-feeling is secondary, or becomes secondary.  To me, this gives Descartes his argument, and CT's critique of Cartesian disengagement becomes weirdly self-contradictory, since (1) it was intended to remind Mr. Descartes that not everything was up to him, that he lived in France, spoke French, and had untold contingencies and connections to things real or imagined; but now, admitting transcendence of some kind, so that I can get outside the group and give up my place ("our own place") -- "no longer to be the one who stands in a certain perspective in moral space" -- now (2) everything is up to me, and I have to figure things out pretty much on my own

We disagree on the stuff about selfhood.  To me the self is much more fragmented and to you much more solid and reliably constant, but that is probably my pathology.

We disagree on Plato and Descartes.  I see the cave analogy, I can imagine Cartesian space; I think of reason as an absolutely new standpoint, but it is not identifiable with any of its results.  I don't buy the rejection implied in Nagel's "view from nowhere"; reason is not a view from nowhere but it is not the natural one -- it is simply, a view not from where you started; Nagel has missed the main point of almost all his arguments. 

We disagree about the transcendence issue.  You (as I take you to argue) are thinking that transcendence is a giant step beyond the starting point in the natural attitude.  I see it as a very small change in perspective.  We are moving the origin, or we enter a new cave.  This is the difference between the worldview we learned growing up and the explicitly learned project of philosophical questioning -- or close matches in other tribes

We disagree about frameworks.  You talk about them as the formation of attention and assert that frameworks are not necessarily failures.  I would say that they are formations (plural) of attention, lots of them, and I think it's wrong to talk about them failing -- this doesn't seem right.  People fail, societies fail.  A guiding framework is like a flashlight.  It maybe doesn't show you everything, but it is not failing (at least when it works).  It's a tool.  The form of life, the inescapable framework, is escapable; and it keeps changing.  The flashlight becomes a torch, beacon, laser pointer, lots of new crazy gadget-ideas. 

We disagree about criticism.  You say that it is a higher order capacity.  To me it is universal and happening all the time, but gets dumb-normalized, co-opted, squelched, messed with, manipulated, left hanging -- it needs an education to flourish

We disagree about the malaise.  I think we should go forward and make more pluralism, cosmopolitanism, criss-crossings-and-i-ching-tosses-or-whatever; and become learned about many things, keep going on with the learning process, questioning, the elenchus

We disagree about the elenchus and Socrates and Hebrews 11, but these are good arguments.

Something useful must be happening between us, since we disagree about so much but in the end we agree about everything essential and as you eloquently state: living without questions is not something that an intelligent person is going to do