Sunday, December 9, 2012

Sources of the Self, Charles Taylor


Sources of the Self, Charles Taylor, 1989

Some notes, clarifications, responses, appreciations, counterarguments /SB, 2012

Brief summary: it's good to have someone to argue with; thank you, Charles Taylor, CT; thank you, Eric Springsted, EOS, for sending me to Taylor

(1) review and criticism

(2) EOS - SB

--------------------------------------------------

(1) review and criticism

CT argues against reductionism in many forms, e.g. reducing arguments to mere struggles for power; merely scientistic accounts; mere talk about values.  He wants to recover the diversity of goods that people care about.  He wants to recover the specific character of their commitments.  He wants to recover their heartfelt, unarticulated understandings of what it is like to want something -- which is, to be an agent -- agency as wielding power on behalf of a desired end -- forces aligned to promote a value.

Some of the commitments that he wants to capture in their reality are: the commitment to political justice; the relief of suffering; the love of family; the importance of friends.

Some themes that he derives from Greek scholarship and especially the leadership of A.W.H. Adkins and E.R. Dodds are: from the many to the one (the gradual development of a coherent self from its precursor fragments); enthusiasm and the Homeric background of possession, being overtaken, overwhelmed, being carried away, beside oneself with passion; thumos, psyche, kardia, etor, ker, noos, phrenes, soma, menos (madness); everything in our natures that "wanders between generation and corruption" (Rep 485b).  Adkins' developmental account becomes an important element in the book.  Snell, Schadewaldt, Jaeger, Gilson are here also -- also later scholars such as Walter Burkert, Richard Onians -- also Nietzsche, Nehamas -- also Hannah Arendt. 

A second important strain of influence derives from psychology -- Jerome Bruner, Kohut, Kernberg, Erikson, Ernst Tugenhat, Freud, Foucault -- writers who explore selfhood in its granular construction up from earliest bits of competence (ego nuclei), to stages, to big assemblages of experience, connectivity and idea-formation (durable incorporations).

A third strain is from social philosophy and sociology and concepts of selfhood that bind human to human in social networks -- Marx, Gadamer, Heidegger, Wittgenstein, the Frankfurt school, Humboldt, Weber, Robert Bellah, and especially Aristotle.

            "One cannot be a self on one's own." "I am a self only in virtue of certain interlocators." "I have conversational partners who are essential to my achieving self -definition."  "A self exists within webs of interlocution." (36)

A fourth strain is from storytellers who narrate the struggle to become a self from many corners of transcendence, elation, depression, oppression, dysfunction, illness, and alienation: Joseph Conrad, Kafka, Breton, Goethe, Hoelderlin, D.H. Lawrence, de Sade, Mallarme, Robert Musil, Poe, Pound, Zola, Yeats, Van Gogh, W. Stevens, Dostoyevsky.  CT mines many writers attuned to their rich interior life, who portray this world as discussion and rivalry and conflict -- Pascal, La Rochefoucauld, Marcus Aurelius, Epictetus; poets; generations of ascetics and puritans closely monitoring their sinfulness and daily temptations to stray from the path; journal writers, aphorists; everyone who "makes the dizzying descent into ourselves" (Andre Breton). 

There are conservative icons such as Strauss, Sandel, Augustine, Shaftesbury, Grotius. 

He is fighting against liberal icons such as Socrates, Descartes, Spinoza, John Rawls. 

Terms of art:

constitutive goods (the conceived order of being into which actions flows -- this defines what 'good action' is, the empowering love that urges forward);

disengaged reason (Socratic reason departing from the current ethos; Descartes' pretensions; rationality as conceived in opposition to parochial attachments);

counter-epiphanic (showing things in their crude, lowly reality and disabusing any sentiment of deeper meaning -- the opposite of transfiguration or transcendence);

hypergoods (goods that exemplify and provide the standpoint from which lesser, regular and ordinary kinds of goods are valued -- second-order qualitative distinctions that define and provide the basis of discriminations in value judgment);

inescapable frameworks (defining cultural and social standpoints and codes or forms of life, within which entire epochs unfold historically -- basic horizons; no framework is shared by everyone, no framework can be taken as the framework, no framework can be accorded the status of a fact; instead, we have traditions, ideologies, supercontexts; for which the question arises, whether adopting them is optional?; also, from which we can become disenchanted; which we can leave behind; a frame of commitments and identifications, a shared space of moral concern; that without which, in normal experience, we would be at sea and not know who or what we are, or what the significance of anything might be; which define a narrative by means of which we assign meaning and contemplate new ideas -- the basis projected meaning; a way of talking about structural requirements for human agency which nonetheless do change and which present themselves to philosophy as a problem; which yet we see from the standpoint of the horizon that we ourselves stand within; which CT conceives as a kind of cultural co-embeddedness, directly opposed to the concept of disengaged reason);

            "To articulate a framework is to explicate what makes sense of our moral responses" -- CT gives an example of this at 541 in discussing how the warrior/honor ethic makes sense of Cicero's talk about self-control as manly dignity that steels us against childish, slavish, cowardly, womanly weakness.  The command relation explains the ability to bear pain with equanimity, developing fortitude, soldierly virtue, scorning pain and death.  The framework defines constitutive goods and hypergoods. 

lifegoods (facets or components of life as actually lived, which spell out what is aimed at, in concrete terms, in the context of a cosmic order of being of constitutive goods);

ordinary life (the life of production and the family, merely infrastructurally important to Aristotle, a merely necessary background to the 'good life' of contemplation and action as a citizen; affirmed for the first time as having central importance for the good life via the Reformation, when it is seen as living in the context of a calling -- dethroning the 'higher forms' of life identified in antiquity; putting simple things in the center and underscoring the import of suffering; the key and world-changing focus of Christianity).

With these influences and this new vocabulary, CT contributes to the human project of understanding itself.  He takes on the crucial and mysterious process by which an organism becomes a person.  This big project deserves our respect and critical review…

Some big problem-regions here are: the push-pull of being a one within a many; the long road to integration by which manyness become oneness; the special circumstances in which some one person breaks out from a big framework and begins to live in a different order of being; the life-context of embedded reason vs. the purity of disengaged reason; and tensions between the method and the results of science. 

Some stages of developing selfhood that CT identifies for critical reflection:

Homeric disintegration
Platonic psychological monism and playfulness about psychological polyphony
Augustinian inwardness
Cartesian disengaged reason
Lockean subjectivity of perception
Protestantism and the affirmation of ordinary life
The Enlightenment and reason becoming overconfident and blind to its other
Romanticism, listening to nature and reading nature, expressivism
Modernism, postmodernism, the hodge-podge world and the hodge-podge self; world-
            pieces and self-pieces setting uneasily with each other
The current conflict space -- trying to get clear about the choices in front of us

Tasks: trace the histories of these various self-conceptions; reveal the power these ideas have for us from their deep sources; trace the sources of our inspirations for the many ways we look at things; describe the resultant situation we face in postmodern times; find a way out

Part of this is the Hegelian history of ideas project -- but going beyond Hegel in the Heideggerian claim that rationality is not a disengagement that grasps what the world looks like without us (supposed neutrality or objectivity or scientific truth) but instead reason is a deep part of our humanity with its own special history -- reasoning is something that cultural co-embeddedness instills in new members of our tribe

A basic CT argument: we move through the world via goals (loves, commitments, values) -- thus to see ourselves as agents (and this is what CT is trying to do) is to see ourselves as pursuing what we are after (what we desire, the things we sight in desire, the character revealed in desiring).  Identity is conferred via a person's sense of the good.  This is a bedrock argument in the text.  "To know who I am is a species of knowing where I stand" (27).  "To know who you are is to be oriented in moral space" (28)

Cultural relativism says: evaluation is essentially a projection of local tradition. 

CT wants to fight against this reduction.  He argues: people do not cherish what they do because their tradition tells them to do so.  Instead, they see themselves as striving after what really is good.  CT also argues: people are largely ignorant of, and not too worried about, the various conflicting desires that emerge in even their simplest actions.  He wants to bring more self-consciousness to selfhood. 

CT argues that over a long period of history there emerges the idea of inwardness, inner depth, the whole interior life of thoughts and feelings that has an odd kind of access to itself via reflexivity and self-consciousness.  Joseph Conrad has described in a powerful way these inner reaches which lie at some distance from ordinary mind in a hidden heart of darkness

The Enlightenment self breaks away from nature by setting up a process of scientifically observing nature.  The Romantic self returns to nature and listens to nature and is refreshed and reanimated by nature.  These strains still conflict in us.  There are stresses, tensions.  We cannot put everything we care about and all of our insights, attractions, constructions, into ONE formula, hierarchy, assemblage, in final form. 

More genuinely, the project is to try to do justice to ALL the things we love.  If we do not do this, we "incur a huge self-inflicted wound" (513,520).

Critique:

CT's conclusion advocates a particular way out from the postmodern dilemma but does not argue for it -- he calls it a hunch, an intuition. CT wants to recover the specifically religious sources of value that help us navigate our life-projects -- but this is a hunch and represents CT as advocating a way out, his particular take, rather than the main work of the book, i.e. to lay out the sources of the self and their history (71, 105, 106, 342, 518)

CT has an important insight in grasping that we move through the world via goals.  However, relying on this insight tends to cloud the sense of self that arrives via our mere thinghood and experiences in which one is not being treated as an agent, or seeking good, as value-maker and value-pursuer.  E.g. a human being is someone who makes choices, but a human being is also someone who gets hit by a car.  If the goal is to see selfhood in its wholeness and all its complexity, we have to face the agency/thinghood divide and figure out some ways of getting at this and working with it; the self has lots of "sources"

CT wants to bring self-consciousness to the project of selfhood but at the same time much of the work attacks self-consciousness in its guise of disengaged reason.  The sense of the self that we get from reflecting on our experience needs better integration with the sense of the self that we get by being part of a tradition.  This is a tension throughout the book and is not resolved successfully.  Pascal says: I do not want the God of the philosophers and scholars, but the God of Abraham, Isaac and Jacob.  In a sense, CT has made this mistake.  He has given us the self of the philosophers and scholars. 

Another weakness here is that CT wants to blame cultural relativism, secular humanism and the big complex mess that we face in the postmodern dilemma for people's current sense of meaninglessness, despair, loss of roots, waywardness, alienation, anomie.  But this is absurd, really, and pretty obviously so.  The despair we feel that opens up the chasm of meaninglessness is a legacy of the (now forever lost) centuries-long dependency on religious dogma.  Godlessness is not the result of cultural relativism.  Cultural relativism and the whole big mess of modernism emerge when God dies. 

We used to say (with Aristotle) that if you raise people with love, material support and a good education, then they will be capable of virtue.  CT recognizes that this model does not work anymore because we are more conscious than our ancestors of "the murkier depths of human motivation" (517).  We see how much more than these simple inputs can change the picture.  (This is why the sense of self as non-agent is so important to an integrated conception of the self … we need to bring in chance, fate, politics, economics, intellectual factors, accidents … then we have a better chance of learning the ropes)

There are two poles on opposite sides: a reductionist account, in which explaining means explaining away, and an idealistic account, in which explaining gets us to see that everything depends on us -- on choices, decisions, human agency, the values we live by

There are things we care about and ideas that move us that are really difficult to square with each other.  Just to take one example: CT describes the change from Aristotle to Augustine as progress; but many writers (e.g. Gibbon) argue just the reverse.  Both perspectives are important and insightful.  But they are irresolvable.  There is conflict.  And CT sees that we cannot reduce everything to one measure or tell only one story. 

CT has a huge insight in talking about the good.  If we want to say what it is about human beings that makes them worthy of respect, you have to talk about suffering, about what is repugnant about injustice, about the awe we feel at the dimension of human life.  But argument does not seem to go from a neutral place that everybody can agree about to what CT calls "insights about moral ontology."  What is this ontology?  Maybe it's our imagination at work.  Our instincts.  Our senses.  Our mode of access to the world (the way the world looks to us includes important differences between things and people).  CT blames pluralism for making it too easy for us to hold incompatible moral ideas without trying to square them together and come up with a coherent view.  Pluralism leads to thoughtlessness.  But this seems absurd.  We cannot blame a larger consciousness about the ways people approach the problem of life for making us less rational or less thoughtful or less willing to do the work of trying to resolve contradictions.  The modern condition is crazy-making (like mortality generally) and needs thoughtfulness.  People make their lives thoughtful or no -- not abstractions like pluralism.  Pluralism is just the reality of the variety of frameworks, which variety is irresolvable, as CT himself spells out very clearly.

"Our identity is deeper and more many-sided than any of our possible articulations of it" (29)

CT claims that it is an exclusively modern problem that people are confused about which account of the good makes most sense to them -- or of human nature, of what makes people worthy of respect.  This is absolutely false.  The ancients faced exactly this problem -- probably every age shows us some of this conflict, confusion, struggle … ancient China, ancient India, Melitus, Egypt under Akhenaton, medieval France. 

There are other problems too; CT's account of selfhood is self-avowedly parochial and only addresses the Western self and probably only a small fraction of this kind of experience.  He seems to be arguing that selfhood is contingent at the root and that Indian or Chinese selfhood and other varieties are not covered by his account; and his Western account has been criticized for its monolithic reading of history ("Taylor's account applies only to views that succeed each other within a continuous history," Martha Nussbaum).  For some reason CT quotes Descartes in French even though Descartes wrote in Latin and never approved a French translation of his works. 

Overall: this text makes some huge steps forward and also makes important mistakes.  In my reading, the spirit of helpfulness in this text far exceeds its shortcomings. 

(2) EOS - SB

boss thanks again for taking the time to do this.  In the end we agree about everything essential and as you eloquently state: living without questions is not something that an intelligent person is going to do; we are going to wonder what a person like this is trying to protect; we would worry about them.  'Course people are probably worried about us, too.  Anyhow your final invocation of something like a test of love or by love is cool: love is the guard watching over being assured; love can see when the big thing that a person is trying to affirm and protect has turned into hatred and become destructive.  I like this kind of love and I will block the way to my skepticism.  Some say that love is blind, some that love gives us eyes to see.  I wrote something recently about philosophy and love and I think lovers of learning will like the comparison of questioning to loving -- and assert that some kinds of love keep us sane rather than driving us nuts -- but in another way we also know that love sometimes goes bonkers, and getting your bearings and having some scrap of sanity may be a helpful companion if part of our loving goes nuts.

Certitude as you define it is part of a big whole -- it is a connection to something larger than just oneself.  It's a group feeling, like Ibn Khaldun talks about.  Since its social it is natural to connect it with the kind of love we were talking about above, that understands when devotion to the cause has degenerated into something base.  There is a kind of connectivity and being part of something that palpably incorporates a background orientation ("inescapable framework") and helps to explain judgments that people make unthinkingly on a daily basis.  The problem is how to problematize this background, or open it to revision; how to understand it, how it changes as well as how it endures.  Certitude without questioning degenerates into a condition we will worry about and which may become destructive -- which often has been destructive -- so we will look for a group-feeling that love hopefully reads correctly, and does not lose its head about, and give up the critical project.  This is taking a lot on ourselves but we have no choice -- we have to rely on what we can do -- sometimes we are called upon to be smart about love -- and when we think of ourselves as playing a part of a big whole, we are using our imaginations to help create the common space in which we live our lives (527).

Our author gives us the following opinion: God loveth adverbs; that is, how you do something is everything, not just that you do it.  The critical element is preserved in a way or modulation of conducting or going on with this project -- the project encoded in our inescapable framework.  And this implies some escape, some transcendence, a distancing from "identification with a particular voice" (526), which works like this:

"Transcending the self in the model I am working with here is to escape identification with a particular voice in the conversation … There is no doubt that we have the imaginative power to step beyond our own place and to understand ourselves as playing a part in the whole … what is not clear is to what degree one can actually assume this standpoint and live it … (526-7). 

CT seems to be dismissive of a bunch of recent views that try to deal with the element of transcendence, which he calls "half-baked reflections on language and the impossibility of full presence."  Probably I don't know the references he is getting at in this note, but to me the main thing is any admission of transcendence at all.  If he admits it, then the relationship to the group-feeling is secondary, or becomes secondary.  To me, this gives Descartes his argument, and CT's critique of Cartesian disengagement becomes weirdly self-contradictory, since (1) it was intended to remind Mr. Descartes that not everything was up to him, that he lived in France, spoke French, and had untold contingencies and connections to things real or imagined; but now, admitting transcendence of some kind, so that I can get outside the group and give up my place ("our own place") -- "no longer to be the one who stands in a certain perspective in moral space" -- now (2) everything is up to me, and I have to figure things out pretty much on my own

We disagree on the stuff about selfhood.  To me the self is much more fragmented and to you much more solid and reliably constant, but that is probably my pathology.

We disagree on Plato and Descartes.  I see the cave analogy, I can imagine Cartesian space; I think of reason as an absolutely new standpoint, but it is not identifiable with any of its results.  I don't buy the rejection implied in Nagel's "view from nowhere"; reason is not a view from nowhere but it is not the natural one -- it is simply, a view not from where you started; Nagel has missed the main point of almost all his arguments. 

We disagree about the transcendence issue.  You (as I take you to argue) are thinking that transcendence is a giant step beyond the starting point in the natural attitude.  I see it as a very small change in perspective.  We are moving the origin, or we enter a new cave.  This is the difference between the worldview we learned growing up and the explicitly learned project of philosophical questioning -- or close matches in other tribes

We disagree about frameworks.  You talk about them as the formation of attention and assert that frameworks are not necessarily failures.  I would say that they are formations (plural) of attention, lots of them, and I think it's wrong to talk about them failing -- this doesn't seem right.  People fail, societies fail.  A guiding framework is like a flashlight.  It maybe doesn't show you everything, but it is not failing (at least when it works).  It's a tool.  The form of life, the inescapable framework, is escapable; and it keeps changing.  The flashlight becomes a torch, beacon, laser pointer, lots of new crazy gadget-ideas. 

We disagree about criticism.  You say that it is a higher order capacity.  To me it is universal and happening all the time, but gets dumb-normalized, co-opted, squelched, messed with, manipulated, left hanging -- it needs an education to flourish

We disagree about the malaise.  I think we should go forward and make more pluralism, cosmopolitanism, criss-crossings-and-i-ching-tosses-or-whatever; and become learned about many things, keep going on with the learning process, questioning, the elenchus

We disagree about the elenchus and Socrates and Hebrews 11, but these are good arguments.

Something useful must be happening between us, since we disagree about so much but in the end we agree about everything essential and as you eloquently state: living without questions is not something that an intelligent person is going to do


Wednesday, November 14, 2012

Religion, Culture, History


My new work Religion, Culture, History: A Philosophical Study of Religion has just been published.

It is available via Amazon at http://www.amazon.com/-/e/B0093EHJ4Y.  Here is an excerpt.


"Thoughtfulness is a good in itself and a pleasure to engage in.  But thoughtfulness brings us to moral conclusions and thus directs us from thought to action. Philosophy serves a purpose and has thus an instrumental role – but not that of upholding a cause, in which it differs from advocacy such as we see in religious life.  Thoughtfulness serves life by examining it. Thoughtfulness serves life by creating more thoughtfulness.

Question: If philosophy is a way of emancipating ourselves from stupidity (superstition, blind conformity, epistemic arrogance), then – once we are emancipated – what do we do with thoughtfulness?  

Answer: We never emancipate ourselves from stupidity – there is no step beyond thoughtfulness."



Monday, October 29, 2012

philosophy as love


Derek Allen, of the Australian National University writes:

Interesting idea about philosophy and love. Personally, I don’t know enough about the subject matter, but others might like to start a thread.

While here, I’ll quote another bit from the book I mentioned:
“… having seemingly exhausted their own mandate … analytic philosophy has begun to turn toward Continental philosophy. Not, alas, as a rapprochement, not by inviting practitioners of Continental philosophy to join the discussion, but only, and as if bored to tears by their own analytic themes, taking up themes (and names like Nietzsche, Heidegger and Deleuze) of Continental philosophy. For the analytic tradition is intentionally bankrupt (this is the internal logic of the analytic method), but although rendered moribund by its own hand, within the profession (aka academic and editorial control) it enjoys the power of the majority or dominant tradition. To keep itself going it means to seize (but not to "think") the spiritual capital of a tradition whose authority is denounced as that of non- or "bad" philosophy."
Bracing stuff.



My thoughts:

You say that you do not know enough about love to discuss the subject, but I think philosophers should not shy away from this subject, since Socrates claimed that his knowledge of love was the sole exception to his general policy of ignorance. 

Then you quote A House Divided: Comparing Analytic and Continental Philosophy, (Humanity Books, 2003).

“… having seemingly exhausted their own mandate … analytic philosophy has begun to turn toward Continental philosophy. Not, alas, as a rapprochement, not by inviting practitioners of Continental philosophy to join the discussion, but only, and as if bored to tears by their own analytic themes, taking up themes (and names like Nietzsche, Heidegger and Deleuze) of Continental philosophy. For the analytic tradition is intentionally bankrupt (this is the internal logic of the analytic method), but although rendered moribund by its own hand, within the profession (aka academic and editorial control) it enjoys the power of the majority or dominant tradition. To keep itself going it means to seize (but not to "think") the spiritual capital of a tradition whose authority is denounced as that of non- or "bad" philosophy."

Philosophy, by this account, has lost the thread from its ancient founding, having become an institution and a dark priesthood obsessed with power.  The religion of emptiness -- intentionally bankrupt -- rendered moribund by its own hand -- enjoying power -- selling its goods by hijacking trends in contemporary culture -- relegating its influences to a lower status -- used goods -- having completed its crossword puzzle -- now free to relax. 

But Nietzsche, Heidegger and Deleuze do not want us to relax.  Like Kierkegaard they say "All existence makes me anxious … the whole thing is inexplicable, I most of all … anxiety may be compared to dizziness … anxiety is the dizziness of freedom … whoever has learned to be anxious in the right way has learned the ultimate."   This is philosophy that is still connected to its origin -- not a puzzle but all-in engagement in being. 

The fundamental experience in intellectual search is exactly the enigmatic situation we are facing in every moment of our lives.  To me this argues that philosophy is metaphysics, first philosophy, cosmology and ontology, before it is logic and epistemology and analysis.  Heidegger explains:

The important distinction between ‘worldview’ and ‘philosophy’ is the distinction between pre-theoretical understanding and explicitly theorized understanding.  Heidegger says that “when someone strives for a higher autonomous worldview, cultivating a thinking free of religious and other dogmas, then one is doing philosophy” (“The Idea of Philosophy and the Problem of Worldview,” War Emergency Semester 1919, Freiburg, section 1).  At the same time, when someone tries to get some distance from all the ‘natural’ attitudes with which he has been raised, and which he has taken on by belonging to different groups – i.e., when this person starts trying to do philosophy – the goal is to develop a comprehensive point of view, a generic frame of reference for interpreting all experience – i.e. philosophy tries to articulate a comprehensive ‘worldview.’  Heidegger expresses this idea in his 1919 lecture course by saying things like “philosophy is metaphysics” and “philosophy’s struggle with the puzzles of life and the world comes to rest by establishing the ultimate nature of the universe realized as a worldview” and “the task of philosophy is worldview.”

The first issue is existence itself and what if anything we can discern about it.  We are trying to think through the experience of being.  But perhaps we get lost in thinking and lose touch with being -- because we are bringing the examining focus to a game, and not to our own lives. 

As it were: we see our love from afar and want to learn more about her, but this desire may become an obsession; then we have forgotten about our love and the happiness we see in her.  -- What is philosophy if not love?


Tuesday, October 23, 2012

with or against Descartes


Charles Taylor (pictured at left) is a Catholic philosopher.  Taylor, Alasdair McIntyre, Michael Sandel, Gadamer, Heidegger and Wittgenstein are all on one side of an important question in philosophy.  The question is, Does the Cartesian project of radical doubt make any sense?  They all answer negatively.  In brief, they argue that human beings are cultural, social, group-raised-and-defined beings, and that the whole project of epistemology becomes questionable when you see human being in its social roots.  Foundationalism won't work, they argue; and representational theories of knowledge won't work either.  The ground on which these thinkers make their case is an examination of human being, including the conditions of human knowledge.  They all argue that human being is a kind of cultural co-embeddedness, and that knowledge, rather than being a grounded structure, or pure receptivity, is a kind of agency that only makes sense in the context of things that we do with other people.  So the image of the passive recipient of objective knowledge won't work.  Knowledge in its root forms is social through and through and is agency through and through.  So: the knower cannot detach from society, as Descartes wishes.  And: the knower cannot detach from desire, planning, intentionality, as Descartes also proposes.  So the Cartesian project fails.

An interesting side-note here is that by arguing against the Cartesian project, all these thinkers end up with right-of-center political views, in which social traditions, habits, cultural life-ways and social prejudices play a big role, perhaps even larger even than objective reason.  Thus the church and traditional religion become important again, after the blows they suffered in the Enlightenment.  This whole trend in philosophy is part of the Romantic reaction to the enlightenment.  

The left wing that stands on the opposite shore here includes all thinkers who think that people have the power to detach from tradition and think dispassionately about reality without the intervening filter of cultural and social mores, traditions and prejudices.  Descartes (pictured at right) is a founding figure here.  Rawls is in this group, arguing for the possibility of thinking via the original position.  Philosophers who focus on the individual, apart from society, are in this group, who see dangers in being absorbed into social groups and losing touch with objectivity because one has unconsciously taken on the attitudes of one's class, gender, caste, culture, religion, ethnicity or other contingent, situational belonging.  Nietzsche, Kierkegaard, Schopenhauer, Freud, Emerson, Thoreau, Dworkin, Kant, William James and Hannah Arendt are all on this side, arguing for the individual's confrontation with the questions of existence, unmediated by social trends.  

Can I understand myself and my world via my own thinking and work?  --- or --- Do I necessarily rely upon, and expressly or covertly incorporate, the big reigning ideas from my society, cult, language, upbringing and zeitgeist?  Are my views merely the consequences of where and when I was born, and who my parents were?

Tu weiming adds something interesting to this problem.  He is saying, as a Chinese person, raised in a Confucian culture, I cannot get away from my background.  But my attachment to my cultural tradition has freed me.  My love for it has opened up the world for me.  I can find my heritage and test the ideas that I care about in my encounter with other peoples' traditions.  I can learn other traditions and languages and expand my world and my self-consciousness via my project in learning.  He asks, but does not answer, the question: When I get into these gains from intercultural contacts, am I working towards finding the core of my existing beliefs, or am I beginning to take a step outside my sphere of cultural reference?  Am I sentenced to a Confucian outlook because I was born into it, or can I change my outlook into something completely new?  He seems to suggest that a new kind of human flourishing is possible via transcending narrow boundaries of self, cult, nation and geography.  This is what he calls "spiritual humanism."  He wants to rethink the humanist project: not as self or other, but as self and other.

Saturday, September 8, 2012

some recent publications

Two of my writings have been published recently -- a study of the dialogue between Jaspers and Heidegger and a study of aesthetics.

My study of  the Jaspers/Heidegger dialogue appears in the Journal of the Existential Psychoanalytic Institute of Seattle (EPIS).  The web address for the EPIS is http://episjournal.com/?p=175.

Here are two excerpts:


"Jaspers sees everyone as a moral agent, called to reach out to the other; this call is essential to selfhood.  The core ethical ought is: become what you are.  But “the thesis of my philosophizing is: the individual cannot become human by himself.  Self-being is only realized in communication with another self-being.  Alone – I sink into gloom – in community – I rise into fulfillment in the work of mutual discovery.  My own freedom can only exist if the other person is free.”
...

"We do not solve the problem of being obsessed with wealth by becoming obsessed with power – or happiness, or goodness, or truth – or anything else.  The solution is not to replace one worry with another.  The solution is to take control of worry – which Heidegger interprets to mean inhabiting the worry – being it – keeping a “firm hold” and a “willful resolution” – concentrating on the fundamental experience of worry and asking the most important questions in a philosophically rigorous manner.  The point is to know and feel “the nature of the intuitive experiences lying at the basis” of philosophical questioning, and not become sidetracked with late developments and refinements of this basic worrying attunement.

Heidegger’s formulations for this ‘taking control’ stress its interminability – this is “incessant actualizing,” “continual renewal,” “constant renewal,” “constantly standing at the starting point.” The end goal is “an infinite process of radical questioning that always includes itself in its questions and preserves itself in them” (this is the last line of Heidegger’s review).
This is his 1920 statement on “thinking without presuppositions” – an idea that he continued to reformulate over the years – later it is called Gelassenheit, for example (“releasement,” or “meditative thinking” as opposed to “calculation” or “calculative thinking,” from Discourse on Thinking, 1959).
The final Heidegger has given up the idea of staying in the process of questioning expectations andpreserving oneself in problematizing experience because these formulations speak to a powerful sense of agency that he no longer feels.  But his quietist or meditative ideas from late years speak to a similar ‘remaining in process’ – e.g. “dwelling,” “staying open to Being,” or “standing in the draft,” to cite a few Heideggerian formulations of similar ideas from the 1950s and 60s.  Philosophy grows out a certain kind of worry.  Initially the task seems to be to take over the worry machine, reset the dials and decide for oneself what to worry about.  Later the task seems to be to convert the worry machine into a listening device and start listening to Being."

My study of aesthetics is called "Lines of Thinking in Aesthetics" and is available from Amazon -- Daimonion Press.  
http://www.amazon.com/Lines-Thinking-Aesthetics-Steven-Brutus/dp/1470167034
Here is an excerpt:



"Socrates is especially drawn to examples that compare physical health to justice and inner harmony, making the legislator a kind of physician for the city; also to the analogy that as medicine is to the body, so is justice for the soul.  He appears to dismiss mere art or mere craft in comparison to true art or true craft; and the defining characteristic of true art, versus its mere appearance, is the care that it takes for the excellence of the thing it is trying to make.  Sometimes he says that this makes the difference between knowledge and wisdom.  Sometimes he says that this is the difference between trying to evoke pleasure and trying to promote the good.  Sometimes he says that craft-art-science emerges from handiwork (knowing hands) which involves hard practice, and that justice is like this and takes practice; sometimes he says that the practice of honesty heals the soul (as medicine heals the body) and makes us happy."